This site includes my past two decades' teaching-n-leaning in Social Science fields, Educational Technology, Art, some of my cross-cultural observations, non-academic/sociocultural critiques, and pasquinades (after retirement). At the current stage, no guest blogs. No advertisements. All rights are reserved.
▼
Pages
▼
Friday, September 28, 2012
Saturday, September 22, 2012
A Discussion on Beauty vs. Artistic Beauty
A Discussion on Beauty versus Artistic Beauty
Li-chin (Crystal) Huang
University of Minnesota-Twin Cities
University of Minnesota-Twin Cities
A Discussion on Beauty versus Artistic Beauty
Table of Contents
Introduction
Research purposes and methods- sencondary data analysis
Literature Reviews
Results
Conclusions
References
Abstract
The enterprise of aesthetic judgment is highly complicated. The writer differentiates the major differences between the concept of “beauty” and “artistic beauty” as part of our team debate for a course work. In this paper, the former refers to a general pleasure response of aesthetic experience. The latter points to particular artistic endeavors, progressing from retinal toward cerebral aesthetic experience and judgments, and is highly contextualized.
The enterprise of aesthetic judgment is highly complicated. The writer differentiates the major differences between the concept of “beauty” and “artistic beauty” as part of our team debate for a course work. In this paper, the former refers to a general pleasure response of aesthetic experience. The latter points to particular artistic endeavors, progressing from retinal toward cerebral aesthetic experience and judgments, and is highly contextualized.
What is
beauty vs. artistic beauty?
Seeking,
presenting, and interpreting what beauty is, permeates most human societies. For example, there is a saying in Japan that
if the length of Cleopatra ’s beautiful nose changed a tiny bit, maybe the
human history would be written quite differently. So as in several sagas in
Chinese history depicting the most desirable and unfathomable beautiful women
(of whom, later some became expresses, royal concubines, or women in power)
contributed to the changes of the Chinese history either in better or worse
directions. This is said to be true of
the Balinese, who say, “we have no art, but do everything the best way we can,”
may be another example that expands the concept of beauty to perceiving and
appreciating in all spheres of their activities those aesthetic values we find
in artworks alone (Battin, Fisher, Moore, & Silvers, 1989).
So, how do Japanese and Chinese define
female beauty? Can human appearances or physicality be works of art? Are there
different aesthetic criteria in judging female beauty between Chinese and
Japanese, and between Westerners and Easterners? What are the differences
between the judgments of female or body beauty versus that of judging
calligraphy- valued as high art in most Far Eastern cultures? Why do Balinese regard that nothing is art
but do the best they can for what? In
short, what is “beauty” versus “artistic beauty” in human endeavors and all
sphere of daily activities as mentioned above?
In searching
for the possible answers, information pertinent to the topic
was collected from books, journals, and the Internet to form as a
secondary data analysis.
Literature Reviews
Generally
speaking, concerning what is beautiful is part of philosophical inquiry located
in the aesthetic domain. Aesthetics is a branch of philosophy, which has
occupied thinker from Plato to the present day. To define perfection and to set
standards of beauty termed aesthetics or, “the science of the beautiful,” was
initiated by German philosopher Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten in 1753.
Baumgarten was considered the first modern philosopher to approach the question
of beauty systematically, introducing the term aesthetics and defining the
experience of beauty as the “sensory recognition of perfection” (Danto, 1997).
His contemporary, Immanuel Kant, expressed a universal, disinterested notion of
aesthetics, which is without a specific purpose and judgments or mere personal
preference toward a beautiful object (Bernard, 1951).
Among these
two quite opposite points of views, I investigate another eclectic definition
of aesthetics from Encarta. It defines aesthetics as: “A branch of philosophy
concerned with the essence and perception of beauty and ugliness, dealing with
the question of whether such qualities are objectively present in the things
they appear to qualify, or whether they exist only in the mind of the
individual; hence, whether objects are perceived by a particular mode, the
aesthetic mode, or whether instead the objects have, in themselves, special
aesthetic qualities.”
Similar to
many philosophical issues, the concept of aesthetics is inherently
debatable. The above definition is no exception. For
example, what and how to “qualify
such qualities”, and what how the “special aesthetic qualities” are in the definition is still
ambiguous and debatable.
However, it points out two
domains worth of attention: one is
“the qualities are objectively present in the things they
appear to qualify”; the other one is
“whether such qualities exist only in the mind of the
individual.” Understanding these
two questions might shed some light on the comprehension of
“beauty” versus “artistic
beauty.”
In order to
understand the concept of aesthetics, the following section reviews several
perspectives from various rationales of philosophers, aestheticians, and social
thinkers dichotomized mainly, into two categories: objective and subjective
accounts of beauty. The former can be
seen that the beautiful qualities are objectively presented in the things they
appear to the qualifications; and the latter is perceived whether the beautiful
qualities exist in the mind of the individual.
The objective account of beauty
In this tradition, I started with Platonic point of view that a relation of resemblance
between the art work and the object it imitates as the key
to the mimetic theory. The
formalism can be traced back to Aristotle’s aesthetically
good- or, actually beautiful- if it
is ordered, symmetrical, and define, and if it demonstrates
each of these virtues to a high
degree. This analysis
we call “formal,” because it focuses on the presence in the object
of certain aesthetic properties, ones that have to do with
the form (as distinguished from
the content) of the object. St. Augustine is another
formalist. His account of beauty was
an object to be beautiful is for it to exhibit unity,
number, equality, proportion and
order, with unity as the most basic notion. St. Thomas
Aquinas was also found a formal account of beauty that rests on three
conditions: integrity or perfection, due proportion or harmony, and brightness
or clarity (as light is a symbol of divine beauty and truth). Shaftesbury
believed that so long as one was disinterested in attitude, one’s judgment that
an object was beautiful was correct as long as the object exhibits “uniformity”
(Battin et al. 1989). Francis Hutcheson
believed that if an object exhibits “uniformity amongst variety,” that object
is beautiful. Joseph Addison believed
that an object was worthy of positive aesthetic judgment if it exhibited
greatness and uncommonness. Up to the 20th century, Moore recognizes the
aesthetics exists in organic unity. Clive Bell refers it as significant
form. Beardsley felt that for an object
to be aesthetically good is must be unified and/or intense, and /or complex,
and be such that it prompts in attentive perceivers a pleasurable experience
characterized by unity, and /or intensity, and /or complexity (Fenner, 2005).
The Subjective account of beauty
David
Hume and Immanuel Kant shed new light on the concept of aesthetics.
Instead of focusing on the aesthetic object, they assumed
that the qualities of attender
made him or her a good judge (2005). Within the Kantian framework,
if a flower is
aesthetically pleasing, but is ecologically destructive--it
could never be ideally beautiful
because ideal beauty for Kant is uniquely a product of moral
values. The objective beauty
of flower is never the same as the ideally/subjectively
beautiful.
In reality, After World War I and World War II, the impact and the
magnitude of
human disasters
provocatively challenged artists to rethink and re-formulate the
conventional ways of perceiving, understanding, and
reflecting on the concepts and
principles of morality, justice, and the meaning of beauty.
Following the same vein,
American painter Philip Guston, who, in the Vietnam War
period, could find no
justification or moral consistency in painting beautiful.
So as in 1967, in conversation with critic
Roger Fry, Marcel Duchamp pointed out that art should do was call up, not a
sensual response, but an intellectual one, which can be interpreted as art
should not stay retinal, but cerebral. His fountain (urinal piece) challenged
our cognition regarding what it means to make art beautiful while the world was
undergoing destruction.
As to the
Emotionalism, argues that art is the embodiment in a public, sensuous medium of
an emotion or a collection to them. The “aesthetic attitude” theorists point to
a certain disinterested quality of mind the artwork invites; and hedonists to
objectify pleasure as principles to judge beauty. Finally, Pragmaticism or
Functionalism points out that art is to promote the common good and empower the
common people as the criteria to judge the beauty of objects (DiBlasio,
excerpted from Weitz, Summer 2005).
Art historian Janson points out that art has both ideas and facts. Aesthetics concerns the beautiful. But, not all art is beautiful to our eyes, but may be to the minds. My question is whether the beautiful is imbedded specifically in the ideas or facts, or both? For Hegel, there are three hierarchically ordered categories of beauty. These include: natural beauty, artistic beauty (behind which lies intentions), and the beauty one finds in decoration and adornment (which is meant to enhance the pleasure). Among the general population when asked what do you like about a picture, the most used term is "pretty" or some variation related to pretty which I refer to Hegel’s first layer of beauty, or Parsons’ non-reflective point of views as well as likening the beauty, realism, and skills. Why do majority of population (as we refer to “untrained’ eyes and minds) prefer beauty defined as realism with intense skills? A discussion from various perspectives will be continued into the following section.
A Discussion on
Beauty versus Artistic Beauty
Santayana in defiance of Kant, says that pleasure is the essence of the perception of beauty, and aesthetic pleasure cannot be divorced from interests. He pointed out that aesthetics, the theory of beauty, in particular for the individual, is concerned with the perception of values that are dependent upon emotional consciousness: appreciations, appetites, and preferences (Fenner, 2003). So, what are the essences of appreciations, appetites, and preferences?
Santayana in defiance of Kant, says that pleasure is the essence of the perception of beauty, and aesthetic pleasure cannot be divorced from interests. He pointed out that aesthetics, the theory of beauty, in particular for the individual, is concerned with the perception of values that are dependent upon emotional consciousness: appreciations, appetites, and preferences (Fenner, 2003). So, what are the essences of appreciations, appetites, and preferences?
During the
last hundred years, aesthetics had been relating to psychology, a field which
has come to equally debatable for its own multiple expansion of
perspectives. In the following sections,
I tried to borrow some understanding from psychology to examine the sensory beauty
and artistic beauty. From the bio-genetic
perspective, all human beings, in general, are born with similar genetic
makeup, such as brains and nervous systems to perceive the imageries and
events. That could explain why some sensory beauty or pleasurable beauty has
commonality. Looking in to the details, we can detect the differences between
sensation versus perception. In
psychology, sensation is the process by which our sensory receptors and nervous
system receive and represent stimulus energies from our environment. Perception
is the process of organizing and
interpreting sensory information, enabling us to recognize meaningful
object and events. The terminology refers to information processing: the
“bottom-up processing” means that analysis that begins with the sense receptors
and works up to the brain’s integration of sensory information. This stage of
processing is similar to Parsons’ first and second steps of art understanding.
According to Parsons people using ideas associated with an intuitive delight in
most painting, as strong attraction to color, and a freewheeling associative
response to subject matter (parson, 1987, p.22) Parsons’ (1987) second
stage “it is true that some paintings
are representational, but they are not really meaningful.” The “top-down processing” means information
processing guided by higher-level mental process, as when we construct
perceptions drawing on our experience and expectations. This processing
corresponds to Parsons’ third stage value “ creativity, originality, and depth
of feeling (1987, p.23); stage fourth of judgments of people using culturally
leaned ideals ( p.143), and the fifth stage of art specialist’s understanding
or plural art world viewpoint (Clover and Erickson, 1997, and 1998).
There is an
important concept related to perception that might aid our understanding the
experience or judgment of beauty. Myers
(2004) remarks, “ As everyone knows, to
see is to believe. As many people also know, but do not fully appreciate, to
believe is to see.” Our experience,
assumptions, and expectations may give us a “perceptual set,” or mental predisposition; that greatly
influences what we perceive. Parsons
(1987), Davis, Gander (2000), and Housen (2000) all point out similar
viewpoints that as progressively exposing to various experiences, people
develop awareness of the characteristic of their own experience and the others’,
a questioning of the influences upon it, and a wondering whether one really
sees what one thins one sees.
Specifically
speaking, it is gene that controls the action of the chemical messengers in the
brain that represents the world we involve with. Some genes, in particular, related to
dopamine, the key neurotransimitter in the brains’ “pleasure center” or reward
system. As dopamine passes from one cell
to another, it signals a pleasurable sensation.
It is normally triggered by action that supports human beings’ survival,
either of the individual or the species in enhancing the physical or mental
state. For example, general public perceive Elvis Presley as one of the most
attractive/handsome and talented male entertainers. For his physical appearance
and music trigger the pleasant sensation through the sight and acoustic senses
that make an individual feel good. The
golden rule in a rectangle is perceived as the most aesthetically beautiful
ratio is another example for a universal beauty account. There can be a
“general” experience or judgment on beauty based on bio-genetic and
evolutionary similarities among human beings. Thus, if beauty taken to such a
broader concept by recognizing any trace of positive aesthetic value as
beautiful which is biologically connected, then pleasure can be the key to
aesthetic value, in terms of abovementioned “general or universal.” As John Ruskin put it, “Any material object
which can give us pleasure in the contemplation of its outward qualities
without any direct and definite exertion of the intellectual, is in some way or
in some degree beautiful” (Ruskin, 1906).
Aesthetics
related to psychology can also be traced back to the concept of
“Associations” proclaimed by Archibald Alison (Fenner, 2003).
He began to focus on the psychology of aesthetic experience instead of the
conditions of aesthetic judgment. Alison emphasized the importance of
imagination in the construction of aesthetic experience. For Alison,
imagination was largely a matter of actively drawing out associations in the
viewer, through what he called “attentive contemplation” of the object/event at
hand. Imaginative associations are not
matters of intellect; they are matters of psychology. He said: The mere presentation of beauty was
not enough to stimulate the sensory receptors into feeling pleasure over the
beauty; the spectator becomes a more active participant. He exercises his
mind, his imagination, and his attentive contemplation, in order to experience
more fully the nature of the object, and in so doing experience the object as
fully aesthetically as he can. Without this mindful/imaginative activity, the
experience is not aesthetic, but one of mere pleasure (Fenner, 2003).
He argued
that aesthetic beauty takes mindful and imaginative mental activities. He
distinguished the sensory pleasure (general) from the aesthetic engagement
(particular). The similar emphasis on psychological state can be found in
Dewey’s concept of aesthetics. He also focused not on conditions of judgment
but on exploration of the psychological nature of experiences. Dewey’s (1934)
account centers on what he calls “an experience:” ” An experience is any garden-variety experience
that one might have which has the character of being maximally unified and
highly meaningful. An experience is a bounded organic whole; when a moment is
sufficient to itself, is individualized, this is an experience. In aesthetic
experience there is a heightened interest in the factors that constitute an experience,
in the experience’s “omnipresent form, in its dynamic construction, in its
rhythmic variety and unity.”
Another well
known theory touches on aesthetics is Maslow’s hierarchy of need- though it is
still debatable regarding this theory.
According to Maslow (1968, 1970), human needs are arranged in a
hierarchy, and individuals must satisfy their basic needs first, before they
can progress to higher needs. In the
following diagram, higher levels in the pyramid represent progressive less
basic needs, people progress upward into hierarchy when lower needs are
satisfied. In the diagram, the aesthetic
needs for order and beauty is the second highest in the progressive
hierarchy. Does it mean that the general
sensory account of beauty happens in the lower level of needs that according to
Maslow, won’t be seen as aesthetic beauty or “an experience” as Dewey called
it? Or such a high level of aesthetic needs have the similar statewide progress
similar to Parsons’ fourth or fifth stage of artistic understanding?
Seemingly,
Maslow’s aesthetic needs of beauty and order might not be located in the sensory level of
pleasure. It is artistic!
Figure
1. Maslow’s hierarchy of needs.
Dickie
(1919) once argued that psychology was not relevant to aesthetics by attacking
Bullough’s view by denying that there is any one thing that we can identify as
the aesthetic attitude. Perhaps, he is
one among the minority side. D.H.
Feldman (1980) remarks that art appreciation and the production of art are
developmental phenomena. They have in
common that they are achieved through sequences of stages or levels, catalyzed
by sets of specialized cultural conditions.
DiBasio (1997) points out the consequences of the cognitive revolution
provided an advantage of using of symbol system that bears directly on the
aesthetic forms of human experience and on the mechanisms of metaphoric expression.
Art does harvest from the psychological research, in particular from the
cognitive domain!
In addition
to the aforementioned beauty perceived in general term, on the other hand,
taste or aesthetic experience and judgment is conditioned mainly by culture,
which is less likely to reduce art to any set of judgments. For example, the
calligraphy of Si-Zhi Wang of Tang Dynasty is the most aesthetically beautiful
works of art in Far Eastern Asia from my socio-cultural perspective. Each calligraphic
character might not arouse the sense of artistic beauty from an audience of an
alien culture.
Battin et
al. (1989) points out that a good many theories of art, in fact less concerned
ultimately with to definitional than with the contextual. They argue that
liking or disliking a thing may be a necessary condition of its being judged to
be beautiful, but it is not a sufficient condition. Wittengstein argues that in
searching for approval for judgments creates
the questions, such as criteria approved by whom, and who should join
the approving group. This is a potential leading to the institutional theories
of arts (Barrett, 1966). Kant too, analyzes beauty mainly by characterizing its
inward effects rather than its outward causes. He remarks that judgments of
beauty is “subjectively” universal. H.W. Janson infers that we cannot escape
viewing works of art and judging the beautiful in the context of time and
circumstance, whether past or present (1991).
Danto
introduced the term “art world” (1964) as “to see something as art requires ….
A knowledge of what other works the given work fits with, a knowledge of what
other works makes a giver work possible (Danto, 1997). He also argues that the
art world of the twentieth century was epitomized by cognition and by
challenge, such as the challenge to the very definition of art: for examples,
Dadaism, and Pop Art. Later it expanded into conceptual art, challenged the
concepts of values. Mapplethorpe, Rene Serrano, Richard Serra, Damien Hurst,
Christopher Ofili, and a host of others have presented works that confront and
provoke the viewers. They assail our values and the contexts in which we hold
those particular values (Fenner, 2003). These value-challenging aesthetics is
undeniable.
Fenner points to an eighteenth-century
movement in aesthetic theory from
formalist, objective accounts of beauty to subject-based,
experiential accounts of
beauty. He argues that an emphasis away from the production
of beauty to what he calls the “artistic” or the “artistically important” is the main theme of the Modern Art. And he suggests that the reason for this is
the move toward subjectivism in analyses of what counts as beauty (Fenner,
2003). This is what I believe that the
main difference between general concept of beauty and artistic beauty lying in
the contextualized understanding. Fenner
also proposes a framework to contextualize the meaning and experience of
aesthetics which I reorganized into the following concept map:
![]() |
According to
his framework, experiencing an aesthetic object, the various contexts provide
different dimensional aesthetic experience and judgments.
Conclusion
As we know the enterprise of aesthetic judgment is highly complicated. The writer differentiates the major differences between the concept of beauty and artistic beauty. The former refers to general pleasure response of aesthetic experience. The latter points to particular artistic endeavors, progressing from retinal toward cerebral aesthetic experience and judgments that is highly contextualized.
As we know the enterprise of aesthetic judgment is highly complicated. The writer differentiates the major differences between the concept of beauty and artistic beauty. The former refers to general pleasure response of aesthetic experience. The latter points to particular artistic endeavors, progressing from retinal toward cerebral aesthetic experience and judgments that is highly contextualized.
References
Battin M, Fisher J, Moore. R, and Silvers A. (1989). Puzzles
about Art- An Aesthetics
Case Book. New York: St. Martin’s Press.
Case Book. New York: St. Martin’s Press.
Clover, F, and Erickson, M. (1997). Viewpoints: Exploring how we understand art.
On ArtEdNet posted by the J. Paul Getty Trust [Available Online]
http://www.getty.edu/artsednet/resources/Viewpoints/index.htm
On ArtEdNet posted by the J. Paul Getty Trust [Available Online]
http://www.getty.edu/artsednet/resources/Viewpoints/index.htm
Danto. A.C. (1997). After the end of art: Contemporary art
and the pale of history.
Princeton. NJ: Princeton University Press.
Princeton. NJ: Princeton University Press.
Danto. A.C. (1986). The
End of Art in The Philosophical Disenfranchisement of Art.
New York: Columbia University Press.
New York: Columbia University Press.
Danto, A.C. (1964) the art world. Journal of Philosophy,
62(190, 571.
Davis, J. & Gardner, H. (2000). Symbolic literacies: the
Developmental portrait research
has produced. In R.S. smith (Ed), readings in discipline-based art education: A
literature of educational reform (pp.257-263). Reston, VA: National Art education
Association.
has produced. In R.S. smith (Ed), readings in discipline-based art education: A
literature of educational reform (pp.257-263). Reston, VA: National Art education
Association.
Dewey, J. (1934), Art as Experience. New York: Capricorn
Books, Putnam’s Sons.
DiBlasio, M. (1997). Essay Review: Harvesting the Cognitive
Revolution:
Reflections on the Arts, Education, and Aesthetic Knowing. Journal of
Aesthetic Education. Vol. 31, No1.
Reflections on the Arts, Education, and Aesthetic Knowing. Journal of
Aesthetic Education. Vol. 31, No1.
Dickie, G.
(1919) Is Psychology Relevant to
Aesthetics? See also E. Bullough’s
The Relation of Aesthetics to Psychology, British Journal of Psychology 10
(1919).
The Relation of Aesthetics to Psychology, British Journal of Psychology 10
(1919).
Foster, A, & Blau, J, (1989), Art and Society – Reading
in the Sociology of the Arts. New
York: State Univeristy of New York Press.
York: State Univeristy of New York Press.
Fenner, D. (2003). Aesthetic Experience and Aesthetic
Judgments. Journal of Aesthetic
Education, Vol. 37, No. 1.
Education, Vol. 37, No. 1.
Fenner, D (2005). Why Was There So Much Ugly Art in the
Twentieth Century?
Journal of Aesthetic Education, Vol. 39, No. 2.
Journal of Aesthetic Education, Vol. 39, No. 2.
Feldman, D.H. (1980). Beyond universals in cognitive
development. Norwood,
NJ:Albex.
NJ:Albex.
Housen, A. (2000) Museums in an age of pluralism. In R.S.
smith (Ed), readings in
discipline-based art education: A literature of educational reform (pp.281-7).
Reston, VA: National Art Education Association.
discipline-based art education: A literature of educational reform (pp.281-7).
Reston, VA: National Art Education Association.
Francis Hutcheson, F. (1971). An Inquiry into the Original of Our Ideas of
Beauty and
Virtue. New York: Garland.
Virtue. New York: Garland.
Jason, W. H. (1991). History of Art, 4th ed. New York:
ARS/SPADEM
Maslow, A. (1968). Toward a psychology of being. New York:
Van Nostrand
Maslow, A (1970). Motivation and personality. New York:
Harper & Row.
Myers, D. (2004). Exploring
Psychology, New York: Worth Publishers.
Parsons, M.J. (1987). How we understand art: A cognitive
account of the development of
aesthetic understanding. New York: Cambridge University press.
aesthetic understanding. New York: Cambridge University press.
Ruskin, J. (1906). Modern Painters. Vol. 1, 3rd ed. (New
York; Thomas Crowell, ) p. 101
Shaftesbury, A. (1964). Characteristics of Men, Manners,
Opinions, Times. New York:
Bobbs-Merrill.
Bobbs-Merrill.
Weiten, W. and Lloyd,
M. (2000). Psychology applied to modern life. CA: Wadsworth/
Thomson learning. P.49.
Thomson learning. P.49.
Wittgenstein, L. (1966). Lectures and conversations on
Aesthetics, Psychology,
andreligious Beliefs, ed. C. Barett. Oxford: Blackwell.
andreligious Beliefs, ed. C. Barett. Oxford: Blackwell.
Friday, September 21, 2012
Sunday, September 16, 2012
Friday, September 14, 2012
Sunday, September 9, 2012
Saturday, September 8, 2012
Friday, September 7, 2012
Monday, September 3, 2012
Sunday, September 2, 2012
Saturday, September 1, 2012
Sept 1, 2012 Many A Mini Poor Boy
http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=ZxYGeTV6fCw
Animals, The House of the Rising Sun
http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=7OqwKfgLaeA
Cat's in the Cradle